The
Tools of Philosophy
In the firsts centuries of the Middle
Ages all philosophers, no matter what
the language was they were writing in,
used ancient logic as a tool for grounding
their arguments: above all, Aristotelian
logic, but also Stoic logic. The Latins,
though, did not have at their disposal
all the texts that formed the Organon
of Aristotle until the 12th c.; up to
that time they only had access to the
part of it called the Logica vetus (or
Ancient Logic), namely those works translated
by Boethius:
the Categories, the De interpretatione,
and the Introduction (or Isagoge) of Porphyry.
Through some of Boethius’ own writings,
but also through Augustine, they came
to know the principal trends of Stoic
logic, the doctrine of signs and of the
hypothetical syllogism. It is only starting
in the 12th c. that translations
from Arabic and Greek reintroduced to
the West not only Aristotle’s writings
on the syllogism and on the method of
science (the Prior and Posterior Analytics),
but also Greek, late-antique, and Byzantine
commentaries on Aristotelian logic. The
12th c. is a crucial period for the development
of logic in the West. In fact, even before
the recovery of the entire Organon, an
original way of analyzing the logic and
linguistics had appeared inside the schools,
arising from the study of two of the liberal
arts, dialectics and grammar. In the
meantime some Islamic thinkers, besides
carrying on the tradition of commentating
on Aristotle, had started to create a
different logic, capable of answering
the new needs induced by the philosophical
use of their own language. Only one of
these texts was translated into Latin,
the Logic of al-Ghazali,
and later it was used by Ramon
Lull to create an original method
of demonstration, different from the Aristotelian
one.
|