Medieval Logics
In the field of logic the dialogue between the three medieval
Mediterranean civilizations was reduced to a minimum. The Byzantines,
that had the entire corpus of Aristotle’s logical works, did
not create any relevant innovations; while the original contributions
of Islamic authors such as Abu Bishr Matta and Yahya Ibn Adi (10th
c.), Abu’l Barakat (12th c.), and Ibn Taymiyya (13th c.) were
not known in the West. In the Latin world, the first century of
the Middle Ages did not see any significant developments of dialectics,
the art of language that ‘distinguishes the true from the
false,’ following the definition given by Alcuin
during the Carolingian period: dialectics uses the devices of the
division of an argument and of a concatenation of equivalent propositions,
adopted often by Anselm
of Canterbury. Writers of the high Middle Ages knew—through
Boethius
and the late-antique encyiclopedias—the
doctrines of the syllogism, both those of Aristotelian origin (the
demonstrative
syllogism, which is verified according to a reference to reality
already included in the premises and according to the formal correctness
of the relationship between premises and conclusion) and those of
Stoic origin (the hypothetical
syllogism, in which the conclusion or consequence can be verified
on the sole basis of the formal relationship between premises).
The Aristotelian
logic, with its ontological and semantic implications (the doctrine
of the universals),
as well as the post-Aristotelian logic, partly coming from the Stoics
and partly from the original speculations of the medieval masters
of logic (logica
modernorum), underwent a radical change inside the municipal
schools during the 12th c. Logical knowledge was systematized
in the 13th c. in the writings of Peter
of Spain and of William
of Shyreswood, while in the 14th c. further logical developments
led to the new devices of formalization and mathematization in the
Merton
school of logic and in the writings of Thomas
Bradwardine; in the 15th c., finally, the work of Paul
of Venice
produced an important system of articulation for all of medieval
logic. The logica modernorum was not the only non-Aristotelian logic
created in the Latin world. In the last decades of 13th c., Ramon
Lull formulated an original logic based on non-Aristotelian
devices: correlatives
and the combinatory
art, which formed the ground for his ‘demonstration through
equiparation’, a demonstration he considered superior to the
syllogistics ones. The Lullian art would be broadly diffused during
the Renaissance, when it was used as an inventive logic (a logic
capable of finding valid arguments) and as a mnemonic and encyclopedic
device.
|