Heritage
of the Middle Ages
The underlying element on the debate whether there is continuity/discontinuity
between the Middle Ages and the Renaissance and/or the Modern Age
was mainly the identification of medieval philosophy with a process
of development in the West that culminated in Scholastics. This
identification is no longer possible today, both because of the
plurality of cultures in which medieval philosophy flourished and
because of the multiplicity of the philosophical positions found
even within the Latin West. Thus, the diverse philosophic panorama
in the 14th and 15th c., once considered a clear sign of the decline
of Scholasticism, is now considered a broad framework for all the
various and complex struggles for change, promoted by the increasing
availability of sources and by the renewal of philosophic problems
typical of the 12th c. From this point of view, we can draw the
same conclusion for medieval philosophy as Marcia Colish has drawn
for medieval culture in general: namely that ‘the ability
to preserve itself, the fascination or the renown usefulness of
medieval culture for post-medieval Europeans varied from field to
field,’ but we can also say the central lesson of the Middle
Ages is that it ‘is possible to keep an organic link with
tradition while critically using it.’ This aspect characterized
in the Middle Ages, as it does even today, the teaching done in
the universities, an institution which represents—though having
changed in form—the most consistent and lasting institutional
heritage of the Middle Ages. If we attempted a detailed summary
of the relationship between medieval and modern philosophy, we can
find continuity inside the process of transformation in that which
Adam Funkenstein defines the ‘theological roots of modern
science.’ Problems such as the omnipotence of God and His
presence in the world, having emerged from the environment of Scholastic
theology and studied by the greatest philosophers of the Middle
Ages, were still present, though in different ways and functions,
in the writings of the great philosophers and scientists of the
modern age: Descartes, Spinoza, Leibniz, and Newton. In addition,
we find continuity in Hermetical
thought and in the possibilities of transforming nature, both
of which are passed down to Renaissance writers and to the occult
tradition (from the Rosicrucian Order to Masonry and contemporary
occultism), which accompanies modernity and constitutes its ‘dark
side’. The durability of an element more marginal—the
interest for Ramon
Lull’s combinatory art—assumed an important role
in the understanding of a relevant part of modern thought, 17th
c. encyclopedism; while the mendicant orders continued to cultivate
the heritage of their medieval ‘champions.’ On the other
hand, instead of continuity, we see a repeated reawakening of interest
for the most original philosophic arguments in medieval Latin, and
above all the ontological proof for God’s existence by Anselm
of Canterbury; while in the logica
modernorum, historians of logic recognize one of the most original
and fundamental developments for the discipline, which seems to
proceed by fits and starts and whose scholars dialogue with one
another across the centuries, as is demonstrated by the interest
of many contemporary logicians for medieval logical research. Finally,
it should not be omitted, as Alain De Libera has noted, the fact
that it was during the Middle Ages that the first (and until now
the one and only) significant cultural exchange with the Islamic
world took place, a dialogue which gave
rise to the transformations of European culture starting from the
12th c. Avoiding the risk of over-idealizing the epoch that saw
also the crusades, it is necessary to acknowledge that we have to
almost completely pass over modern age to find in our history a
multifaceted dialogue with the cultures of ‘the others.’
|