Philosophy
in the Latin World
Between the 6th and 7th c., the collapse of teaching institutions
and a general climate of instability stimulated an awareness in
various intellectuals that it was necessary to safeguard and transmit
the cultural heritage of antiquity in new forms adequate to the
times. For these reasons Boethius
planned to translate antique philosophical texts, a project he completed
only partially; Cassiodorus
articulated an educational curriculum focused on the tradition of
the liberal
arts in the context of monasticism;
and Isidore
of Seville constructed a new type of container for the transmission
of knowledge, the encyclopedia.
In the early Middle Ages it is theology and the rise of new theological
problems that create a new space for philosophy. Both in the monasteries
and in the schools born during the Carolingian reform (9th c.),
Augustine of Hippo is the principal author and guide for the relationship
between the liberal arts and Sacred Scripture and for reflection
on theological problems; the various phases of his thought influenced
the authors who participated in the intellectual debates
of the time (on predestination, on the Eucharist, and on the soul).
Only one of these writers, John
Scotus Eriugena, created a real and true systematic philosophy,
but in its own time it won few followers. In the 11th c., from the
debate between those for (Berenger
of Tours) and against (Peter
Damian and Lanfranc
of Pavia) the use of dialectics
in theology, a real medieval philosophy began to take shape in Latin,
and with Anselm
of Canterbury we see the beginnings of rational argumentation
applied to the doctrines of the faith, as well as the first medieval
meditations on language. In the 12th c. the study of logic
gained even more currency and new fields of research were created:
Abelard
was an innovator in the disciplines of logic, theology, and ethics,
while the masters
of Chartres, making use of new philosophic and scientific texts
translated
from Arabic, developed a philosophic interpretation of the creation,
comparing the Biblical narrative with Plato’s Timaeus. In
this way, a new space was opened up also for natural philosophy.
The monastic culture underwent important internal changes with the
work of the masters
of St. Victor and Hildegard
of Bingen, while Bernard
of Clairvaux was strongly opposed to the masters of philosophy
who taught in the schools. It was, however, the new philosophy that
would emerge from the conflict victorious: the universities
themselves are proof of this process of transformation, insofar
as they were structured around a philosophic curriculum based on
the interpretation of Aristotle, that changed the relationship between
philosophy and theology. After an initial phase of mistrust and
prohibition, with Albert
the Great the assimilation of Aristotelian philosophy began,
grounded in an Arabic interpretative framework and integrated with
Neoplatonic elements. The teaching of Albert produced various results:
the radical Aristotelianism of the Latin Averroists,
the Christian Aristotelianism of St.
Thomas, and the valorization of Platonism in German students,
most important among whom is Eckhart.
The inescapable confrontation with Aristotle had a different turn
in the thought of Bonaventure
of Bagnorea, who developed the Franciscan notion that the created
world is a sign of the creator into a philosophical reflection,
beginning a line of thought that we find also present in the scientific
work of Robert
of Lincoln and Roger
Bacon; while the Catalan Ramon
Lull followed an original philosophic route, working out a method
of demonstration inspired by the logic of al-Ghazali.
At the end of the 13th c., the belief that Aristotelianism and Christianity
could be completely integrated gave way to the search for new approaches
bythinkers like Duns
Scotus and William
of Ockham; and in late-Scholasticism all philosophical approaches
developed in the confrontation with Aristotle's thought would become
fixed in the schools and different ‘viae’.
|