Reason
and Faith
At the beginning of the medieval period, religious unity under
Christianity was the only factor of homogeneity that had survived
the breakup of the classical world: all medieval philosophers in
the West and in Byzantium are Christian, and a philosophic notion
of evangelical revelation had already been developed, from the Logos
of John’s Gospel to the philosophy of Augustine and the Greek
Fathers. There is no tension between reason and faith in Boethius
or in Pseudo-Dyonisius;
instead, in the West, tension arises when rationality, understood
as the capacity to define and distinguish (dialectics),
becomes the mark of Carolingian power. In the debates
of the Carolingian period, it is possible in fact to individuate
how the use of dialectical reason came into conflict with the need
to not contradict the concepts that justify the traditional ways
of mediation with the sacred, namely the basis of ecclesiastical
power. And neither in the dialecticians nor in the anti-dialecticians
is there a conflict with reason as such, but rather there are limits
to its applicability to the doctrines of the faith (the divines
mysteries and the sacraments). It will be the solution of Anselm
of Canterbury expressed in the formula of ‘faith seeking
understanding’ (fides quaerens intellectum) to legitimize
once and for all rational inquiry, opening up the possibility to
create a theology,
even though the ecclesiastical institution will make its presence
felt on the dangers of rationalism through the condemnations of
Abelard
and the masters
of Chartres in the 12th c. If we compare this situation with
the contemporaneous changes occurring in Islamic philosophy, we
note that the social context is different. In the 11th c. in the
West, ecclesiastical power, philosophic research, and theology are
interwoven in the same environment and at time practiced by the
same people, whereas in the East, religious and social life are
dictated by the literal interpretation of the Koran, and thus the
followers of Kalam and the mystics of Sufism work outside the spheres
of power, if not in direct opposition to them. In addition, the
first Hellenizing philosophers (al-Kindi
and al-Farabi),
who pursue their studies in the shadow of political power, are very
attentive to never question philosophically the absolute transcendence
of God. In this context, then, we see an interesting analogy with
the situation in Byzantium, the institutional separation between
philosophic research and political and religious power. Even in
Islam, however, the tension between philosophic research and faith
later (11th-12th c.) appears with the reaction of al-Ghazali
against Avicenna,
and above all, when the thought of Averroes
is banished from the schools: the position he had explicated in
the Short Treatise on relationship between philosophy and religion
was the last, albeit the most strong affirmation of the primacy
of Aristotelian reason in the Islamic world. The appearance of works
of Aristotle
exacerbated again the problem of the relationship between religion
and faith, never completely resolved even in the Latin world. The
Aristotelian notions on the eternity
of the world and on the soul
as form of the body contradicted the concept of divine liberty
and encouraged a naturalistic anthropology. From the prohibition
of 1210, which linked Aristotle and heresy, to the condemnations
at the end of the century (1270 and 1277), the tension between theologians
and philosophers was ever present, while inside the mendicant
orders the way of approaching philosophy and its relation to
the doctrines of faith was quite different. At one extreme we have
the Catalan philosopher Ramon
Llull who was close to Franciscan positions, arguing it was
possible to prove the truths of the faith with ‘necessary
reasons’ articulated through an original method of demonstration,
the ars combinatoria. Nor did the christianized Aristotelianism
of St.
Thomas win unanimous consent; several of the theses condemned
in 1277 were Thomistic philosophical positions. Finally, the separation
between the world of faith and that of rational inquiry (philosophy
and science) characterize the modern via based on the philosophy
of Ockham,
from which positions rooted in skepticism and/or sheer faith arise
during the last two centuries of the Middle Ages.
|