THE PORTRAIT OF THE LOVER
Webpage
Contents
Portrait of the
Lover: A Brief Summary of
the Book
There are many ancient stories about the lover, the beloved, and the
portrait:
Pygmalion and the statue that comes to life is surely the most famous
story, but there are many
others. The plots of these stories reveal
a great deal about ancient Greek and Roman concepts of love, desire,
death, art, and representation. Laodamia is united with the dead shade
of her husband Protesilaus, and
keeps a statue of him in their bed; Admetus keeps a statue of his dead
wife Alcestis in his bed: the
portrait of the lover thus becomes a consolation for lost love, a
paradoxical sign of both absence and
presence.In other stories, men actually fall in love with images,
conflating the beloved and the portrait into
a single character - and in the story of Narcissus, all three
characters collapse: Narcissus is lover, beloved,
and portrait simultaneously. These portraits are more than a
reproduction of a person: they are the
representative of that person, a component part of that person's
identity. Stories about the portrait of the lover
thus provide a metalanguage for ancient culture, an exploration of
human life through an anthropology of the
image.
Translator's
Introduction One of the central themes of this book
is that of "worsened"
reproductions: what Augustine calls resemblance in deterioribus, the
lamentable situation that arises when a
copy fails to resemble its original perfectly and instead resembles it
only roughly, partially,
insufficiently.
As examples of reproductions in deterioribus, Augustine lists such
phenomena as dreams and optical
illusions,
family resemblances between parents and children, along with portraits,
sculptures, and
other
works of art. But he could also have included translations under this
same heading. Much like the
legendary
painters and sculptors whose adventures constitute the main subject of
this book, translators are
likewise
condemned to create reproductions that are always in deterioribus. Of
course, if a goddess
were
to intervene - as Venus did for Pygmalion, bringing his beloved statue
to life - this English
Portrait
of the Lover might become as bright and vibrant as Maurizio Bettini's
Ritratto dell'amante. But in
the
absence of divine intervention, I would like to explain something about
the original Italian context of
this
book, and to say a few words about what inevitably gets lost in the
translation. First, Maurizio Bettini represents a school of Italian
classical
studies
that may be rather unfamiliar to American readers, even to American
classicists. His focus is on the
anthropology
of ancient Greece and Rome, and in this effort to elucidate the meaning
of ancient cultural
models,
every bit of textual evidence becomes potentially significant. The
canonical authors all have their
place
here, of course, and the pages of this book are filled with references
to Homer, Herodotus, Euripides,
Cicero,
Vergil, Horace, and so on. But side by side with Homer and Vergil the
reader will find such
authors
as Palladius, Censorinus, Scribonius Largus, Fulgentius, Hesychius,
Pollux, and Minucius Felix,
not
to mention all the anonymous scholiasts of late antiquity who provide
Bettini with some of his most
precious
insights into the cultural models of ancient Greece and Rome. The
results yielded by such an
approach
are dazzling and extremely persuasive - but the reader may find it
disconcerting at times to
confront
this crowd of oddly named strangers and unfamiliar sources. At such
moments, it might be helpful
to
invoke a metaphor that Bettini often uses to describe this sort of
work: what we are looking at is a
cultural
mosaic made up of thousands of textual tiles, oddly shaped,
varicolored, all of which must be
continually
combined and recombined, so that we are always having to re-read each
time that we read something
new,
taking a fresh look at everything over again as we assemble some
different part of the puzzle.
Of course, to take such a synthetic approach to these ancient texts
(and
bits of texts) depends on a particular assumption: in Bettini's words,
"this sort of dialogical
mosaic
implies that there is a given structure in culture, that beliefs are
part of a system of meaningful
signs."
And this is the second point of departure, the other major difference
between Bettini's work and that
of
many American classicists. Bettini is deeply influenced by
structuralism and the semiotic theory
of
signs; consequently, the reader will find frequent references in these
pages to such scholars as Claude
Lévi-Strauss,
Jean-Pierre Vernant, Emile Benveniste, Roman Jakobson, Vladimir Propp,
Algirdas Julien
Greimas,
and Umberto Eco, among others. It is these scholars who provide the
methodological assumptions
according
to which Bettini proceeds, and it is from these authors that he derives
some of the key
terms
of his argument. In particular, Vernant's work on the anthropology of
the image in ancient Greece is an
essential
element in the project which Bettini undertakes in this book.
Fortunately for English-language
readers,
many of Vernant's relevant essays on this topic have recently been
translated in a
collection
entitled Mortals and Immortals (edited by Froma Zeitlin). But - I
hasten to add - there are no
required
readings, no prerequisites for this book. The important thing to keep
in mind is simply that Bettini's work
here,
like that of Vernant, Lévi-Strauss, Benveniste and the rest, is based
on a fundamental belief
in the meaningfulness of human culture. The resulting combination of
structuralism and semiotics is
thus
quite different from other varieties of post-structuralism with which
English-language readers may be more
familiar,
as represented by such scholars as Derrida, Foucault, and Lacan, to
name only a few. When
Bettini
uses the terms "signifier" and "signified" he is not preparing to
launch into a deconstructionist
spiral
of philosophical abstraction; instead, he is speaking about meaning,
and the way that meaning is communicated
between
one person and another. Accordingly, I have often chosen to translate
his significato
as
"meaning" or "message" rather than simply as "the signified" (the
Italian significato is not as
technical
as the English "signified"), so as not to imply a deconstructionist
program which would be very out of place
in
the pages of this book. But by and large the reader will find that
Bettini writes an almost
jargon-free
style of scholarship. In fact, the form in which Bettini most often
makes his argument is that of a story,
and
of the meanings that stories can convey: as he himself explains, the
Portrait of the Lover is a
story
about two lovers and a portrait, and all the variations that ancient
culture played upon this famous
theme.
The entire book is built around such stories (and of course one story
leads to another story, and
another...
as stories tend to do). Along the way, Bettini makes a series of
complex arguments about the many
different
meanings of `the image' in ancient Greek and Roman societies, and the
different cultural models
(religious,
political, psychological, etc.) in which images could become involved.
But the guiding thread of
the
discourse always takes the form of a story, and it is the succession of
stories that gives the
book
its shape and structure. This leads to the third and final observation
in this apology of the
translator:
Maurizio Bettini is not only an extraordinary scholar, but he is also a
writer of immense talent, and a
very
inspired teller of stories. This, more than anything, is what gets lost
in translation. In many cases, I
have
simply had to resign myself to not being able to translate the elegant
word play and boundless humor
of
Bettini's original Italian, with its sly irony and often elaborate
allusions. As a rule, when forced to
choose
between the scholarship and the writing, I have always chosen the
scholarship, preferring to make the
argument
and the method as clear as possible. This was the only choice that I
could make, at least
according
to Augustine's pessimistic (but probably correct) theory of
resemblances in deterioribus. Because this
Portrait
of the Lover is a translation, it cannot help but prove inferior to the
original. But if
I
have been able to present Bettini's main arguments clearly, I hope that
this English version will be of some use
to
anyone who shares an interest in ancient Greece and Rome, so that we
might thus bring to life - again
like
the lucky Pygmalion - those cultures that have for so long been
presented to us only in the frozen
inertia
of marble statues. The statue that comes to life is just a fantasy, of
course, a fairy tale, a
story...
but these are stories that we cannot do without. In the end it is the
stories that matter most of all: which is
perhaps
the principal lesson that this book has to teach us, and the secret of
its success.
Summary:
Part One. The
Portrait of the Lover
(Chapters One - Twelve) There are many ancient stories about the
portrait of the lover, with
plots
involving a lover, a beloved, and a portrait. These stories are made
possible by specific cultural models,
revealing
ancient Greek and Roman beliefs about love, desire, death, art, and
representation. The first
portrait
of the lover was created to replace an absent lover, by tracing his
shadow on the wall: the
portrait
of the lover is thus connected with shadows, and also with the "shades"
of the dead, like the archaic Greek
kolossos
which was a physical embodiment of the psyche or eidolon of the dead
person in the form of a
stone
image. Laodamia is united with the dead shade of her husband
Protesilaus, and she keeps a statue
of
him in their bed; Admetus keeps a statue of Alcestis in his bed, and so
on. In other stories, men
fall
in love with actual statues: the beloved and the portrait are conflated
into a single character (as is
also
the case in Lucretius's philosophy of love). In the story of Narcissus,
all three characters collapse:
Narcissus
is lover, beloved, and portrait simultaneously. The portrait is more
than a reproduction of a person:
it
is that person's representative, and forms of a part of that person's
identity. The portrait of the lover
functions
as a sacralizing object, the embodiment of a vow of fidelity: if that
vow is broken, the image can
come
to life and seek revenge. Stories about the portrait of the lover thus
provide a metalanguage for
ancient
culture, an exploration of human life in terms of the anthropology of
the image.
Summary:
Part Two.
Other Adventures of the Image
(Chapters Thirteen - Eighteen) Stories about the portrait of
the lover make it clear that
the ancient
Greeks and Romans treated the image differently than we do, and the
second part of this book considers
these
cultural practices in greater detail. Images had to be treated with
respect because they were considered an
actual
representative of the person, and the way that images were treated was
of profound concern in
ancient
society, and there are many anecdotes, myths, and social regulations
pertaining to the
involvement
of images in the life of the human community. Because images are
somehow a perfected form of
reality,
they can also foretell the future: like visions in prophetic dreams,
paintings and other
artificial
images were ominous harbingers of the future. Images were thought to
somehow convey identity in a
profound
and deep sense, which is not surprising, given that ancient identity
was very often constructed in
terms
of resemblance, especially the family resemblances shared between
fathers and sons. Sons are in some
sense
the "portraits" of their fathers, and all the anxieties and
uncertainties of these family
relationships
could be displaced into the world of images, and the stories that were
told about them in ancient
Greece
and Rome.
Chapter Summary:
Chapter One. Introduction
Francesco Petrarch possessed a portrait of his beloved,
Laura, and
in a lyric poem (Canzoniere 78) he compares himself to Pygmalion, who
was able to bring to life the statue
of
his beloved. The stories of Pygmalion and Petrarch are examples of the
"fundamental story" that is
examined
in this book: the many different stories that can be told about a
lover, a beloved, and a
portrait.
Petrarch's words about Laura's portrait exemplify some of the qualities
that will typically
characterize
the paradoxical, fundamentally ambivalent status of the portrait in
this relationship. The portrait
engages
and attracts the lover, and is often a superior, idealized version of
the beloved - but it cannot
engage
in reciprocal relations, it cannot speak, it cannot love; the portrait
exists in the absence of the
beloved,
it is a replacement for the beloved, so that the lover does not feel
himself to be alone - but the lover is,
in
fact, very much alone. The portrait simulates the life, the presence of
the beloved, and brings consolation
-
but it is also an inanimate object, proof of the beloved's absence, and
hence a source of despair. These
are
the basic qualities of the relationship between the lover, the absent
beloved, and the portrait.
By
considering these stories and their variations it is then possible to
ask a series of essential questions
about
the cultural models that make these stories possible: the meaning of
love, death, desire, art, and
representation.
Chapter Summary:
Chapter Two. A Potter Who Was
Not Jealous The portrait of the lover is a consolation, a
substitute for the absent
beloved,
and is produced from regret, unsatisfiable desire (Greek pothos, Latin
desiderium). The Greeks and
Romans
said the first portrait was made by a woman about to lose her lover:
she traced his shadow and her
father,
the potter, modelled it in clay. The portrait is linked with the shadow
(Greek skia, Latin umbra),
and
with the shade of the dead (Greek eidolon or psyche, Latin umbra). In
the famous story of Laodamia
and
Protesilaus, Protesilaus's shade returns from the Underworld to rejoin
his wife; in other
versions,
Laodamia keeps a statue of Protesilaus in their bed. This connection
between the shade and the
statue
is parallelled by the archaic Greek kolossos, an uncarved stone statue
that represented the dead
person's
afterlife. The portrait is also linked to dreams, another partial
representation that can console the
bereft
lover (Laodamia dreams of Protesilaus). In Aeschylus's Agamemnon,
Menelaus's grief over losing
Helen
is expressed through statues and dreams, and also prints (Greek
stiboi), either Helen's footprints,
or
the bodily impressions she left in their bed. Pythagorean texts also
consider footprints and bodily
impressions
as signs that identity and "represent" an absent person. These cultural
synonyms - portrait,
shadow,
shade, dream, footprint - yield many variations on the story of the
portrait of the lover. The portrait
represents
the absent beloved, in a dense emotional atmosphere of grief, loss,
desire, and hope.
Chapter Summary:
Chapter Three. The Story of Admetus,
and the True Portrait of the Lover After
Alcestis has traded her life for his, Admetus dreams
about Alcestis
and keeps a statue of his dead wife in their bed (the parallel presence
of portraits and dreams). In
Euripides's
version, Admetus says that embracing the statue he "has his wife, yet
not having her." Euripides's
Helen
uses the same words to describe the ghost which Paris takes to Troy (he
"has her yet not
having
her"). Dreams, ghosts, and portraits are all paradoxical examples of
having and not having, of
presence
and absence. Embracing the statue of his dead wife, Admetus calls out
her name: the name is
another
image that identifies and represents an absent person. Most
importantly, Admetus swears undying
fidelity
to his wife: the portrait is a pledge, a vow. Admetus will love only
the statue; he will take no
other
wife. Ancient Roman inscriptions provide non-literary evidence for the
portrait as a sign of fidelity.
Allius
consoles himself with a portrait of his dead wife, Allia Potestas,
vowing he will take it with him into the
tomb
when he dies (much like Admetus); Cornelia Galla adored the effigy of
her dead husband (much
like
Laodamia). The "true" portraits of the lover and their poetic
variations are constructed on
the
basis of the same cultural model: the image represents the absent
beloved, serving as consolation for the
surviving
lover and as an expression of devoted faithfulness, even after death.
Chapter Summary:
Chapter Four. A Plaster Dionysus
Apuleius's Metamorphoses features a portrait of the lover:
Thrasyllus
murdered Charite's lover Tlepolemus in order to marry her, but Charite
is instead devoted to a
portrait
of the dead Tlepolemus, an image made to resemble the Roman god Liber
(Greek Dionysus). Tlepolemus
then
appears to Charite in a dream, and tells her about the murder. Charite
avenges his death, and
then
kills herself: a tragic Laodamia who also avenges her dead husband. The
practice of representing the
dead
in the form of Dionysus was widespread in Rome, and is criticized by
Statius in a poem written to
console
the widow of the poet Lucan. She keeps a portrait of her husband, calls
out his name, dreams about
him:
but she does not confuse him with Dionysus. Why worship the image of
the dead in the form of
Dionysus?
The religion of Dionysus was linked to resurrection and rebirth: the
Titans dismembered the infant
Dionysus
and cooked his body, but his heart was preserved in a plaster statue
until the god returned to life.
Plaster
was symbolically connected to birth, generation, and preservation;
according to some myths, mankind
itself
originated from the plaster-like substance that was produced when Zeus
blasted the Titans with lightning
as
a punishment for having killed Dionysus. The plaster in which the god's
heart was preserved is a
variation
on the portrait of the lover: a memorial to the departed dead, and a
hope for that person's miraculous
rebirth
and return.
Chapter Summary:
Chapter Five. The Sign Stained
by Reality The portrait of the lover is a
metalanguage for ancient
cultural models
of death and fidelity. The first portrait was a consolation for an
absent lover; portraits were also
supposed
to provide consolation to those grieving for the dead: in Fulgentius's
false etymology, the idol is
idos
dolu (Latin species doloris), an "image of grief," and many Christian
authors (Minucius Felix,
Lactantius)
considered idolatry to have begun with cults of mourning for dead
kings. Imbued with emotion, the
portrait
is considered more than a likeness of a person: it "is" that person, a
part of that person, based
on
both similarity and contiguity, metaphor and metonymy. Likewise, the
ghost of the dead is more than a
likeness:
it "is" that person, in a debilitated, partial state - like the
portrait. In Peirce's
terminology,
the portrait is iconic (similar to its object) and indexical
(physically connected to its object). This indexical
quality
allows the portrait to function as the sacralizing object in the
swearing of a vow (Greek horkos,
following
Benveniste's analysis): the sacralizing object is a metaphorical
reminder of the absent person, but
it
embodies that persons' agency, and can punish violators of the oath.
For Dio Chrysostom, the person
has
a "son" or a "wife" in his portrait, and it is an act of adultery to
rededicate an old statue to a new
recipient,
a violation of the fidelity embodied in the image.
Chapter Summary:
Chapter Six. Incredible Loves
Ovid's Pygmalion loved a statue that came to life at his hands, but
other
versions say that Pygmalion was an insane tyrant engaged in a repulsive
affair with a lifeless statue.
There
are many stories about men who loved statues: unhappy, even disgusting
stories, because the statues
can
never reciprocate love. Historical tyrants like the Roman emperors
Tiberius and Caligula were also
notoriously
infatuated with images (frequently obscene). Jensen's novel Gradiva
(made famous by Freud's
analysis)
provides a modern version of love for a statue: like Ovid's
Metamorphosis, the Gradiva
has
a happy ending in which the statue becomes a woman in the end. In terms
of the "fundamental story" of this
book
- stories about the lover, the beloved, and the portrait - these
examples show that the beloved and
the
portrait can combine: the beloved "is" the portrait. The portrait does
not represent an absent beloved,
but
is a love object unto itself. But this was not considered appropriate
behavior: men in love with statues often
suffered
the same mythical fates as men who committed incest. To love a statue
violates the rules: the
statues
are defenseless, and must be protected from undue aggression. Precisely
because they are physically
passive,
they become objects of desire in cultures where the male sexual subject
values most highly a
passive
sexual object: these ancient stories about "incredible love" for
portraits are stories about men,
and
their desire for perfectly passive, mute and beautiful objects of
desire.
Chapter Summary:
Chapter Seven. The Story of the
Cruel Painter In many stories about the lover, the beloved,
and the portrait, the
lover
is an artist: lover of the beloved, and author of the portrait. Pausias
loved Glycera, who was famous for
making
garlands. In his devotion to her, he learned how to paint every kind of
flower: Glycera perfected both
his
love and his art. In contrast, Arellius was a notorious Roman painter
who painted goddesses with the
faces
of his girlfriends, profaning the sacred with his own amours. In Poe's
story "The Oval Portrait," a
cruel
artist marries a beautiful woman and decides to paint her portrait: as
he paints, he gradually
steals
the life and vitality from his wife, until finally he has finished the
perfect portrait (which he loves
desperately),
only to discover that his wife is dead. The narrator of Poe's story is
obsessed by the painting's
perfect
"life-likeliness" of expression: as the painter exclaims when he
finishes the portrait, "this is really
life,
life itself." In Poe's aesthetic, such "life-likeliness" was an
undesirable quality: "The mere imitation,
however
accurate, of what is in nature, entitles no man to the sacred name of
`Artist.'" The artist who
confuses
life and art (or loves art more than life) commits a terrible error. In
the case of Poe's cruel artist, it
is
as if the portrait were an adulterous woman, an unworthy concubine,
acting as the artist's accomplice in the
referent's
assassination.
Chapter Summary:
Chapter Eight. Lucretius
In Lucretius's analysis of simulacra in De Rerum Natura, the portrait
replaces
the beloved even when the beloved is still present. The lover may
embrace his beloved, but he is
grasping
at an image, an illusion. For Lucretius, the wounds of love are real
wounds, lovesickness is a real
disease.
The lover's body is purely physical, grotesque and disgusting. Unlike
the light-hearted fictions
of
Ovid's Ars amatoria and Remedia amoris, Lucretius's love is hideous and
real. Lucretius's theory echoes
the
story of the portrait of the lover, but now the presence of the beloved
in the form of images
(dreams,
the beloved's name, etc.) is only a continual torture. In the Aeneid,
Vergil's Dido is also tormented by
images
of the absent Aeneas. For Lucretius, even when the beloved is present,
the lover still grasps at
simulacra,
scraping the surface of the beloved body, wounding and wounded in
return. Love is a hopeless
devouring:
but unlike food and drink, the beloved cannot be properly consumed. The
lover is a toy in Venus's
hands,
who excites in him an empty craving for images. Epicurus's views on
love were apparently not
so
harsh; Lucretius has taken the Greek theory of eidola and developed a
tormented theory of impossible
love.
In the legend of Lucretius's biography, he was supposedly the victim of
a love potion, and died from
desire:
the poem and the legend (even if it is not true) are both desperate
stories of love.
Chapter Summary:
Chapter Nine: Narcissus and the
Twin Images Ovid's Narcissus loves his own image:
here lover, beloved,
and portrait
become one. When Narcissus sees himself, he is fatally afflicted with
love. In ancient erotic theory,
the
eye was a locus for emotional emanations, and also for jealousy (as in
the evil eye: Greek baskanon,
Latin
fascinum). The Narcissus story is a warning about the dangerous powers
of the erotic gaze. But
there
is a less famous version: Pausanias says Narcissus loved his twin
sister, and when she died,
Narcissus
stared at reflection to see his lost twin. Dead twins are also replaced
by images in the stories of
Romulus
and Remus, and Athena and Pallas (and the Palladium). The practice of
replacing a dead twin with
an
effigy is widespread in traditional cultures. Twins are essentially a
pair, and the absent brother or
sister
must be replaced by an image, just as the portrait of the replaces the
absent half of a romantic pair. In
Roman
culture, lovers could be seen as siblings; a male lover could be called
"brother", a female lover
"sister"
(as in examples from Plautus, Propertius, Petronius, Martial), with no
implications of incest.
Siblings
have a reciprocal relationship of affection and identity, and as such
can stand outside or even in
opposition
to the standard married couple. Aristophanes's speech in Plato's
Symposium gives a mythical origin to
the
pair of lovers: Zeus divided the primordial humans in two, so we are
always seeking our other half.
Chapter Summary:
Chapter Ten. The Insult
After her funeral, Propertius's lover Cynthia visits him in a dream.
She
criticizes him for not observing her funeral rites; she is jealous of
the new woman that has taken her place
in
Propertius's house. This woman has insulted Cynthia's image by melting
it down for gold; she punishes
the
slaves for mentioning Cynthia's name (the name is also an image).
Cynthia is especially fearful that
Cynthia's
mirror will be filled with the new woman's image. Cynthia is very
concerned about how her images will
be
treated after her death, and whether the surviving lover will be
faithful to the portrait of the
lover.
Cynthia's mirror does not just reflect images, but retains traces of
her presence; like the portrait, the
image
in the mirror is tangibly connected by sympatheia to the person (as in
Statius's poem about the image of
Flavius
Earinus captured in a mirror). Real mirrors, as Eco has shown, do not
work this way; but
these
are the mirrors of myth and stories. In another poem by Propertius, the
Roman matrona Cornelia
returns
from the dead to visit her husband. She is not worried that her images
will be mistreated, and she
asks
her husband to engage in a dialogue with her image, as if it were able
to reply. The portrait of
the
elegiac lover is threatened by betrayal and infidelity, but in the
ideal Roman family, the portrait of
the
wife is regarded with dignity and respect.
Chapter Summary:
Chapter Eleven. Seduction and
Vendetta Names, power, riches, even physical features are
passed from father to
son
in patriarchal societies, but the reproductive process involves women.
In such societies, the women are
like
images: women have an autonomous, self-contained meaning, but they
always "refer" to men.
They
embody the men's honor, and the men will defend the women (their honor)
at all costs. In The Stone
Guest,
Pushkin's version of Don Juan, the Commendatore is Donna Anna's
husband, not her father: but she
is
still "his" woman. When Don Juan seduces her, he invites the statue of
his dead rival to act as his
accomplice;
the offended statue comes to life and murders Don Juan (the opposite of
Perseus, who
defeats
his wife's lover and punishes him by turning him into stone). The
statue embodies fidelity (so Ovid's
Dido
venerates a statue of Sychaeus), and if the statue is insulted, it can
exact punishment. Many
ancient
stories describe the statue's revenge, especially the revenge of
heroes' and athletes' statues. A
medieval
story tells how a man accidentally married a statue of Venus by placing
a ring on her finger.
He
could not marry his human bride until Venus relinquished her claims. A
similar story tells how a man
accidentally
pledged himself to an image of the Virgin: but Mary insists on her
claims and the man becomes
a
monk. The images are "binding," with serious consequences for the lover
who associates too
closely
with them.
Chapter Summary:
Chapter Twelve. The Justice
of Death Standing Up Because the image is the
embodiment of a vow, it also the
power to
enforce that vow: the image is justice. Statues are especially able to
exact revenge: they increase in
size,
and free themselves from immobility in order to pursue the offender and
punish him. In the
cultural
imagination, the statue operates along two symbolic axes: it is "death
standing up" (death made to look
like
life), and it is "mummified life" (a living creature that looks dead).
As such, the statue is a truly
uncanny
object (following Freud and Jentsch's terminology): it looks like a
living creature but seems dead,
or
it is a dead thing that seems suspiciously alive. Jakobson analyzes the
statue in similar terms: the
statue
is an embodiment of life in a durable exterior form; it is an image of
continuing life. By
definition,
the statue thus combines both life and death, like the paradox of
absence and presence in the portrait of the
lover.
The statue has the same motionless, cold character of someone who is
dead, with the exterior
aspect
of someone who is actually alive. The statue of the Commendatore that
can uncannily come to life
to
punish Don Juan ("mummified life") and the kolossos that functions as
the double of death in
archaic
Greek culture ("death standing up") define the two ends of that
symbolic range which the statues inhabit in
our
cultural imagination.
Chapter Summary:
Chapter Thirteen. The Gaze
Pygmalion's statue opens her eyes and turns to look at her
lover. In
the beginning, Greek statues had legs that were welded together and
eyes that were shut. they lacked motion
and
vision, two essential signs of life. As soon as the statues were given
free-standing legs, they could
run
away, and had to be tied down with chains (Pausanias describes several
such examples). Daedalus was
the
first to open the statues' eyes, and many legendary images were
supposedly able to return the
spectators'
gaze. In Roman culture, the act of looking back and returning someone's
gaze - respicere - is a
fundamental
component of social contact and communication. Love relationships also
demand this
reciprocity;
gazes of love must be returned. But Ovid's Anaxarete refuses to return
her lover's gaze; he
commits
suicide, and Anaxarete turns into stone when she sees his corpse. As
she stands and stares out
the
window - prospiciens - Anaxarete becomes a statue. It is an aetiology
of the Venus prospiciens
of
Salamis, the Greek Aphrodite parakyptousa. Ovid's prospiciens belongs
to the Roman paradigm of the
reciprocal
gaze, respicere; the Greek parakyptein instead means winking or
glancing. This Aphrodite
parakyptousa
derives from the Near Eastern "woman in the window", a cult
representation of Astarte
connected
with sacred prostitution. Over time, the Near Eastern image became a
Greco-Roman story: in Ovid's
version,
a woman who only agreed to pro-spicere out of the window at her lover's
corpse, never
returning
- re-spicere - his gaze of love.
Chapter Summary:
Chapter Fourteen. Respect
Because portraits are representatives of people, they command respect.
Tiberius
punished anyone who took Augustus's image (on a coin, on a ring) into a
latrine or a
brothel.
Tiberius's obsessions are paralleled by the superstitions expressed in
the rules of Pythagoras: images
should
not be taken into unclean places, etc. One's own image also commanded
respect: Scribonius Largus
complains
that people are more careful in choosing a portrait painter than in
choosing their own physician.
Because
of this close connection between person and image, the fate of the
image foretells the person's
fate,
as in historical anecdotes about Caesar, Vitellius, Domitian, Galba,
Otho, etc. Caligula even kept
a
cult statue of himself which was dressed in the same clothes as the
emperor. The image and the referent
were
made to exist in simultaneity (the image as a mirror of life). Statues
could also represent entire
classes
of people, as in Quintilian's dilemma: "The image of a tyrannicide
should be placed in the gymnasium;
the
image of a woman should not be placed in the gymnasium: a woman killed
a tyrant." A woman's
image
could not appear in the male gymnasium; images of men could not appear
where the cult of the Bona
Dea
was being celebrated. Conversely, the impious matronae of Juvenal's
sixth satire insulted an
image
of their own womanhood by urinating on a cult image of the goddess
Pudicitia. The images command
respect
(or are the victims of disrespect) for a culture's fundamental
categories of identity.
Chapter Summary:
Chapter Fifteen. Premonition
In Terence's Eunuch, the hero sees a picture of Jupiter committing
adultery,
which inspires him in his own amorous escapades. The picture is a
premonition of his own fate. In
Plautus's
Mostellaria, the tricky slave Tranio invents a similarly ominous
picture: a crow plucking the
feathers
of two old vultures, just as he is plucking the feathers of two foolish
old men. In Plautus's
vocabulary,
the word graphicus - "like a picture" - means "perfect." Against
Plato's insistence on the
inferiority
of the images, Plautus considers the picture an ideal form of reality.
Such images can disclose the future,
as
in historical anecdotes told about images of Galba, Pompey, etc. There
is a contrast here between Homer's
Odysseus,
who hears his adventures in a song on Phaeacia, while Vergil's Aeneas
sees his
adventures
decorating a temple in Carthage. Petronius's Encolpius also sees his
unhappy love affair
depicted
in paintings, and Clitophon (the hero of Achilles Tatius's romance)
sees his love for Leucippe
prefigured
in a painting. Likewise, when Leucippe is about to be kidnapped, the
hero is warned by two omens: the
flight
of a hawk pursuing a sparrow, and a painting of the story of Tereus and
Philomela. The image
is
an enigma that announces the future, like images of prophetic dreams,
or the premonitory words of
omens.
In both literature and life, images of vision and of sound are signs to
be interpreted; we ignore
them
at our peril.
Chapter Summary:
Chapter Sixteen. Resemblance
Augustine considers dreams, mirrors, and family resemblances to be
resemblances
"in deterioribus", inferior copies. Family resemblance was a Roman
obsession. Catullus
hopes
Torquatus's son will resemble him perfectly; Ovid's Hypsipyle and
Seneca's Andromache praise their
sons
for resembling their fathers (unlike Martial's Cinna, whose children
resembled his wife's lovers).
The
male factor governs reproduction: patres patribus, as Lucretius says.
But images perceived
during
conception also produce resemblances: in Heliodorus's Ethiopica, the
daughter of Ethiopians is
white
because her mother looked at a painting of Andromeda when she was
conceived. Body fluids can also
produce
resemblances. Breast-milk even produces paternal resemblances because
milk supposedly
derives
from insemination. Faustina was sprinkled with a gladiator's blood when
she conceived
Commodus,
who later played the gladiator. Commodus had a twin, and Fronto praises
their resemblance to
Marcus
Aurelius: the philosopher-king needed twins to reflect both sides of
his identity.
Roman
nobles acquired cognomina from actors who physically resembled them, a
practice apparently related to
the
"double" of Roman funeral rituals, in which an actor played the role of
the dead man. Chariton's
Callirhoe
holds Chaereas's image to her womb, anticipating that their son will
resemble his father. The son
is
a portrait of the lover: Vergil's Dido wishes Aeneas had given her a
son, and she embraces Ascanius in
Aeneas's
absence. Phaedra claims to love the "young Theseus" in her stepson
Hippolytus. In
Artemidorus's
Oneirocritica, dreams of portraits and mirrors symbolize children:
images and reflections of
their
parents.
Chapter Summary:
Chapter Seventeen. The Doll
In 1889, a sarcophagus was excavated in Rome. It contained the remains
of
Crepereia Tryphaena and her beautiful doll. The word for doll in Latin
is pupa, in Greek kore - and
both
of these words also mean the "pupil," the "girl" in the eye. The doll
is a tiny mirror that reflects
the
world at large, and dolls were often interred with miniature tables,
chairs and other small utensils. Unlike
other
images, the dolls' articulated joints simulate movement; the castanets
in their hands simulate sound.
The
doll has a nude body that can be dressed; like a person, the doll can
change her external appearance.
Dolls
do not have referents as other images do. The doll is an
auto-referential sign: the simulacrum
of
a girl that pretends to be a girl. These physical features imply
certain behaviors: the girls would play
with
their dolls, dressing them, combing their hair, making them walk.
Lactantius thus mocked pagan
religion
as nothing more than men playing with big dolls of the gods. On the eve
of their wedding, Roman
and
Greek girls dedicated their dolls in a temple of the goddess (as
Juvenal tells us). This is why Pascoli
called
Crepereia's doll a "doll denied to Venus"; Crepereia did not live long
enough to see her wedding. By
giving
up their dolls, their `virginal' double, girls renounced their
childhood. The doll is another kolossos:
an
image that captures a person's fleeting identity in a permanent form.
Chapter Summary:
Chapter Eighteen. Image,
Mirror, and Homo Suus Seneca gives a lurid description of
Hostius Quadra's use of mirrors to
heighten
his sexual pleasures (a debauched autoscopy). Accused of witchcraft,
Apuleius had to defend
himself
on the charges of possessing a mirror, and his Apology also contains an
apology of the
mirror
itself: Apuleius claims the mirror image is superior to manufactured
images because it changes to
perfectly
reflect its referent at every moment. But the image in the mirror is
impermanent; manufactured
images
have the virtue of durability. The mirror image is impossibly close to
its referent, which
is
why Narcissus's reflection cannot be brought to life like Pygmalion's
statue: Narcissus is already that
living
image, the homo suus (as Apuleius says) of his reflection. In Plautus's
Amphitruo, Sosia
confronts
his double on the same stage (that ille ego, his alter ego), and there
is a struggle for identity.
The
image is a substitute for its referent; but the double is a rival.
Heracles attacked a statue of himself, and
the
statue attacked him in return. Images, on the other hand, are intended
as a replacement for the absent
person.
But Plato (in the Phaedrus) argues that portraits, like writing, suffer
from the absence
of
their "father", from the living voice or living person which they
reproduce. The dying Agesilaus did
not
want to leave images of himself behind for precisely this reason: the
homo suus is exposed to all sorts
of
dangers in his representation as an image.